A disgusting piece of “manufacturing consent” from Canada.
There
are plenty of ideas that are impermissabe to talk about. So why this?
What’s the agenda?
Should older people lose the right to vote?
Some
have argued that disenfranchising the elderly would allow younger
people to make decisions about their future, but is it really that
simple?
4
July, 2017
In
Christopher Buckley’s satirical novel, Boomsday, a Generation X
blogger and emerging PR star suggests that to deal with the social
and economic strain of a large and aging Boomer population, the
government should offer people incentives to commit suicide by the
age of 70. In addition to being offered perks like free Botox and no
estate taxes, those who opt to “voluntarily transition” to death
after retirement are to be treated as patriots and heroes on par with
veterans. Resistance to the proposal is understandably intense and
widespread. But the novel does provoke an important question: What
should democracies do when the interests of the elderly appear to be
at odds with the interests of younger generations?
One
proposal mooted in philosophy circles over the past few decades is to
disenfranchise the elderly—that is, eliminate the right to vote at
age 70 or some other appropriate upper threshold. The idea is that
once citizens reach a certain age, they will be less concerned with
our social, political, and economic future than younger generations
and much less likely to bear the long-term consequences of political
decisions and policies. In that case, their votes ought to be
discounted, or eliminated altogether, to ensure that the future is
shaped by those who have a real stake in how it turns out. But would
disenfranchising older citizens be air?
Consider
two principles of political legitimacy and the way they appear to
unravel in the context of intergenerational justice. The affected
interests principle holds that those whose interests are affected by
political decisions ought to have a say in those decisions. One is a
free citizen, the argument goes, only to the extent that one has
opportunities to shape the laws and policies to which one will be
subject. Without those opportunities, we face a democratic deficit. A
second principle—political equality—holds that those who
participate and are affected ought to have an equal say in the
selection of decision-makers and policies. This is the ideal that the
notion of one-person-one-vote is intended to meet.
In
the context of intergenerational politics, these principles come
under pressure.
Decisions made by older generations will affect the
interests of younger and unborn generations, but those younger
generations will themselves have less or no say. Moreover, as some
argue, older citizens have greater incentives to deplete natural
resources, underinvest in infrastructure, accumulate public debt and
ignore the environment. Polls of top political issues show that
concern for the environment and education declines with age. Grandma
votes against carbon taxes and recycling programs, and Grandpa votes
against education spending? So take away their right to vote and let
younger people make decisions about the future.
But
before disenfranchising older citizens, consider some objections. In
the first place, a policy to disenfranchise the elderly rests on some
questionable assumptions. Although evidence suggests that seniors
sometimes vote in ways that discount the future, younger citizens
also vote in self-interested ways that can lead to costs being passed
on to future citizens. Support for free university and college
tuition, for example, serves younger citizens’ interests but, if
financed through debt, effectively passes the costs to future
citizens. Similarly, parents who support lower taxes so they can pay
for childcare might be as much of a threat to long-term
infrastructure investments as seniors voting for more spending on
long-term care. For almost every reasonable policy preference, a case
can be made that it imposes costs on future generations—even if
only an opportunity cost.
Moreover,
a proposal to disenfranchise the elderly rests on a rather narrow
view of what the right to vote represents. Although voting is a
mechanism for expressing policy and leadership preferences, it is
also a central means by which democracies recognize the moral and
political equality of citizens.
Disenfranchising the elderly might
eliminate one source of short-term thinking in politics, but would
also reduce politicians’ and policy-makers’ incentives to address
the legitimate needs and interests of older citizens. So long as
older citizens are still living citizens, a fair and legitimate
democracy must continue to recognize their political equality and
provide them with means to influence decisions that will affect their
interests.
Frustration
with the policy preferences and omissions of older citizens is a
long-standing complaint of younger citizens. Future generations will
no doubt continue to shake their heads at many aspects of the world
they inherit. The challenge for living, and especially older,
generations, is to vote and engage in politics in ways that go beyond
self-interest. The challenge is to recognize that although future
generations cannot impose costs on past generations, future citizens
can and will judge those who lived before them and will have the
final say over how we and previous generations will be remembered.
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: only a member of this blog may post a comment.